Hipster Cop from Sparrow Media on Vimeo.
Friday, 30 December 2011
Friday, 23 December 2011
Prometheus (official high-definition trailer)
I was online last night and saw how fans were counting down in "real time" till the official release of the first trailer. As you can see from the poster, as per the first film, a "big dumb object" (to use Peter Nicholl's term) features prominently. While it's pleasing to see some evidence of continuity, there may also be a real danger of moving quickly from the sublime to the ridiculous: have a close look at the trailer below, and be sure to freeze it at around 44 seconds in. If you look to the right, very closely, you'll see a humanoid figure who resembles the enormous head in the poster. I really hope then that the Space Jockeys don't prove to be a race that resembles the silly Cenobites from the Hellraiser films (or that other similarly nattily attired villain in Dark City).
To be fair though, I don't have much to go on yet, so I should probably wait till next August before passing judgement. I'm going to be taking in some new material, not specifically related to this film, over the course of the next few days; hopefully it might inspire me to drop in here again to post something about the kind of horror I'd like to eventually see in a science fiction film.
Sunday, 18 December 2011
Rise of the Planet of the Apes is already starting to look like dated science fiction
By 2037 the federally funded chimpanzee research population will "largely cease to exist" in the United States. Advances in the development of other research tools, including cell-based tests and other animal models, have rendered chimpanzees largely nonessential as research subjects, the committee noted.~National Academy of Science, Dec 15; Science Insider, Dec 15
An invaluable resource from the Scottish Council on Human Bioethics
If you're a researcher or a concerned private citizen, then you will agree with me that it is just fantastic to have such an exhaustive list at your fingertips, which includes dramas and documentaries, all tagged to assist your searches:
Film Topics
Abortion (9)
Biomedical Research (14)
Bionics and Cyborg Technologies (8)
Care of the Elderly and Geriatrics (3)
Creation Identity - Sperm, Egg and Embryo Donation (22)
Eugenics and Genetic Enhancement (37)
Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide (28)
Human Cloning (31)
Human Dignity - Full Moral Status (10)
Human Embryology (16)
Human Genetics (14)
Human Sexuality and Biology (1)
Human Transplantation (17)
Human-Nonhuman Hybrids and Chimeras (11)
Neuroethics and the Neurobiology of Moral Responsibility (1)
Organ Trafficking (13)
Psychiatry (34)
Surrogacy (5)
Xenotranplantation (9)
Film Types
Documentary (118)
Drama (165)
Abortion (9)
Biomedical Research (14)
Bionics and Cyborg Technologies (8)
Care of the Elderly and Geriatrics (3)
Creation Identity - Sperm, Egg and Embryo Donation (22)
Eugenics and Genetic Enhancement (37)
Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide (28)
Human Cloning (31)
Human Dignity - Full Moral Status (10)
Human Embryology (16)
Human Genetics (14)
Human Sexuality and Biology (1)
Human Transplantation (17)
Human-Nonhuman Hybrids and Chimeras (11)
Neuroethics and the Neurobiology of Moral Responsibility (1)
Organ Trafficking (13)
Psychiatry (34)
Surrogacy (5)
Xenotranplantation (9)
Film Types
Documentary (118)
Drama (165)
Thursday, 15 December 2011
The only living witness...
Depressing as it is to read speculations about China one day launching electromagnetic pulse bomb attacks against the United States, I suppose at least this pic offers a salutary reminder that things could be even worse if a omnicidal maniac ever had the means at their disposal to deliver destruction on an even larger scale. So don't tell me that this blog never looks on the sunny side of life, right?
There's no way for me to be sure of course, but I'm constantly amazed at the numbers of requests for help I've noticed editors get from Chinese students looking to get into MIT and the like to study computer science. Many of the applicants refer to their interest in hacking/security issues, so I can't help wondering if the ulterior motive is sometimes to later use this knowledge for cyberwar (including accessing the knowledge bases of foreign corporations to learn how they make their products, so their Chinese competitors can attempt to copy and improve them).
I don't want to make this sound like Sinophobia though, not least because I think the political science and computer science departments of any university in the West you can name are in all likelihood equally complicit in state security issues. With regard to political science, for example, one need only consider the critiques of South East Asian Studies as being too closely aligned to the objectives of the U.S. State Department, given its downplaying of the significance of revolution as a developmental logic in this region, in the interest of emphasizing functionalist systems theory instead.
Having said that, the fact remains that China's comparatively low ranking on the Press Freedom Index indicates it is inherently more difficult for its Fourth Estate to "witness" and thereby preempt the kind of realpolitik I've referred to in this post.
There's no way for me to be sure of course, but I'm constantly amazed at the numbers of requests for help I've noticed editors get from Chinese students looking to get into MIT and the like to study computer science. Many of the applicants refer to their interest in hacking/security issues, so I can't help wondering if the ulterior motive is sometimes to later use this knowledge for cyberwar (including accessing the knowledge bases of foreign corporations to learn how they make their products, so their Chinese competitors can attempt to copy and improve them).
I don't want to make this sound like Sinophobia though, not least because I think the political science and computer science departments of any university in the West you can name are in all likelihood equally complicit in state security issues. With regard to political science, for example, one need only consider the critiques of South East Asian Studies as being too closely aligned to the objectives of the U.S. State Department, given its downplaying of the significance of revolution as a developmental logic in this region, in the interest of emphasizing functionalist systems theory instead.
Having said that, the fact remains that China's comparatively low ranking on the Press Freedom Index indicates it is inherently more difficult for its Fourth Estate to "witness" and thereby preempt the kind of realpolitik I've referred to in this post.
Wednesday, 14 December 2011
Monday, 12 December 2011
Transhuman Space
It's been around for a while now, but time has not diminished its power to provoke debates about the myriad ways in which transhumanism may play out (in the distant future), thanks to the game's detailed world-building. I think Transhuman Space could even be used as a teaching aid. I like to consider some of its central themes alongside my earlier post on AIs, moral consideration etc. To the future!
The sliding scale of robot intelligence: We have non-sapient AI (NAI), low-sapient AI (LAI), and Sapient AI (SAI). Also their template IQ bonus is dependent on their program complexity.
Two kinds of brain uploading. "Ghosts" where the brain is destroyed in the process, and "shadows" where the brain survives but the AI simulation isn't as good.
Transhumanism is banned: Largely averted, though various societies ban some Transhumanist technologies - the Islamic Caliphate bans ghosts, the European Union bans radical human genetic engineering, and so on.
What measure is a nonhuman? Legal attitudes vary greatly by country, usually AIs and Uplifts are property and Bioroids are treated as permanent minors while Ghosts and Parahumans are full citizens but there are exceptions. For example the EU gives full citizenship to Bioroids and SAI while the Caliphate treats SAI as people and Ghosts as abominations (my guess is they believe infomorphs have souls). (tvtropes.org)
The Eight Day
This made me think of the character "Coyote" from Kim Stanley Robinson's Mars trilogy. But I should defer instead to the statement of the artists responsible for the work.
Makis Voridis
So this will mean austerity measures will rain down on the Greek people like blows from an axe. Derridata emailed me something on a not unrelated note:
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=MjovTRfj2Gc
I'm a Judeo-Christian morality with a Greco-Roman intellect
It's the way we're short-wired
It's a civilising force that demands respect - from the Baltic to the Straits Of Gibraltar
A blue flag gold star sparks a brand new empire
Ours to build, ours the choice
I'm in an European Super State
Every citizen required to debate!
Why are the proud descendants of Plato paying off more debts accommodating NATO?
We the caretakers of democracy no longer tolerate this hypocrisy
Baltic to the Straits Of Gibraltar
A blue flag gold star sparks a brand new empire
Ours to build, ours the choice
I'm in an European Super State
Every citizen required to debate!
- Old Europe
I'm a Judeo-Christian morality with a Greco-Roman intellect
It's the way we're short-wired
It's a civilising force that demands respect - from the Baltic to the Straits Of Gibraltar
A blue flag gold star sparks a brand new empire
Ours to build, ours the choice
I'm in an European Super State
Every citizen required to debate!
Monday, 5 December 2011
The welfare state: why we need a "Jerusalem for all"
This appeal to the inclusiveness of the British welfare state harks back to the post-war period. It is offered at a time when moves are afoot in Britain to make it a mandatory requirement for chemotherapy or radiotherapy patients to have to report for job interviews. As a part-time personal carer for someone with cancer myself, I am so shocked beyond belief that I really don't know what to say. Anyway, the speaker in the video is so eloquent I don't think I could add much.
All I'll say then is that the idea of appealing to a "Jerusalem for all", which acknowledges Britain's fine past welfare legacy, indeed comparable to Australia's at that time in many respects, can, I believe, be clearly distinguished from comparisons of any continuity between, say, the Scandinavian welfare state, and Nazi policy. I would have quoted Roger Griffin to this effect, but he did not give me permission to cite his reaction on this blog, so I'll refer interested readers instead to something else I've come across. Check out page 266 of the following book, which refers to British historian of science, Paul Weindling (Weindling basically argues that Nazi eugenics were different from the very outset from the Scandinavian program).
Indeed, it is fascinating how in the present British context there is such critical awareness of the odious legacy of Nazi "Sonderbehandlung" (check out the comments thread of the post I've linked to here if you're curious).
Thursday, 1 December 2011
Bringing it all back home....
Just remember, the police started using helicopters after their proven success in the Vietnam War, so it shouldn't really come as much of a surprise that moves would be afoot to now introduce drones as well. Will this be for covert surveillance only (sinister enough), or will we see these things armed as well? And if they are to be armed, how long will it be till a missile is "accidentally" launched into the next demonstration by the Occupy movement or something similar? Trust me, it will never happen to the Tea Party.
It reminds me of that wonderful line from Alien: "the company must have wanted it (i.e. the alien creature) for their Urban Pacification Unit."
"Idea of civilians using drone aircraft may soon fly with FAA - latimes.com: "The Federal Aviation Administration plans to propose new rules for the use of small drones in January, a first step toward clearing the way for police departments, farmers and others to employ the technology."
It reminds me of that wonderful line from Alien: "the company must have wanted it (i.e. the alien creature) for their Urban Pacification Unit."
"Idea of civilians using drone aircraft may soon fly with FAA - latimes.com: "The Federal Aviation Administration plans to propose new rules for the use of small drones in January, a first step toward clearing the way for police departments, farmers and others to employ the technology."
Let me guess: you're feeling safer already, right? |
South Korea to trial robot prison guards
It is just wrong on so many levels So may we all look forward to the day when we toil in private prisons assembling Microsoft products under the watchful eye of our robot overlords!! |
Tuesday, 29 November 2011
Some comments on the themes of "Alien" and the new leaked "Prometheus" trailer
The name of this blog and the pic of the Space Jockey are all drawn from the movie Alien (which as a kid gave me my first sense of the connections between biology and technology), so I might be expected to comment on the leaked trailer for the prequel which has been doing the rounds in the last 24 hours, and disappearing at an equally rapid rate thanks to threats from 20th Century Fox . There was still a poor quality version left on YouTube when I last checked, but I urge anyone who might be interested to instead wait for the official release (which is why I am not posting that trailer here).
Evolutionary theory has often figured in science fiction as a powerfully resonant topic, a privileged point of departure for the staging of a variety of highly charged concerns and conflicts. In some narratives, the positing of a shared kinship between humans and other animals provokes revulsion at the implied refusal of any claim to human preeminence in the greater scheme of things. But the erosion of "Man" as a putatively ontological category and the prospect, moreover, of reality as a Joycean "chaosmos" of perpetual change or metamorphosis can also be depicted affirmatively. The theoretical elaboration of an evolutionary universe need not exclusively elicit horror and anguish. It may also prompt the speculative imagination to extrapolate a future for what might be dubbed "the post-human body becoming." In this essay I’m going to examine a number of exemplary responses in science fiction to the advent of modern evolutionary thought. Discussion will focus in particular on John Carpenter’s 1982 version of The Thing and Octavia Butler’s more recent XENOGENESIS trilogy as evolutionist narratives offering respectively traumatized and affirmative perspectives on a world in which, as Heraclitus long ago put it, "everything flows and nothing abides, everything gives way and nothing stays fixed."
The original film was very important for my personal development and I would like to be able to say more about this once Prometheus is released. All I will say for now is that my expectations are not that high for this prequel because the key to the original's success was that it was largely based on H.P. Lovecraft's maxim, "atmosphere, not action." So no need for exhaustive explanation either, which forces us to use our own imaginations instead. But how can the prequel respect this when everything so far suggests it will be attempting to explain everything. Drawing on the term used by sci fi critic Peter Nicholls, I can also say that what really fired my imagination as a youngster was the Nostromo crew encountering "a big dumb object" i.e. the Space Jockey on Acheron LV-426. This incredible sequence, the greatest I have ever seen, sticking with the terminology favored by Nicholls, Clute et al, instilled in me a "sense of wonder". This was tempered by the knowledge that the warning signal meant there was no possibility of being enchanted by the kind of "cargo cult" qualities associated with the properties of other mysterious xenoarchaeological artifacts, not least the monolith in 2001: A Space Odyssey. Unlike Dave Bowman then, there is no lebensphilosophie style personal transfiguration from crossing a threshold, given how everyone who walks around the derelict is eventually killed by the alien; starting with the necrogenesis scene (better known as the "chestburster scene"), when male crewmember Kane gives "birth" to the alien that implants itself in his body in the derelict's egg chamber (although it could be argued on the basis of the deleted scene featured on the DVD that Captain Dallas [and Brett] is forced to undergo a metamorphosis by being incorporated into the creature's life cycle; however, this is so horrible that it is probably as far from the "exalted" sense implied by transfiguration as one can imagine).
Mentioning Clute et al shows that over the years I've realized that Alien draws on certain conventions of science fiction, but this has only enhanced my appreciation of its qualities. In addition to being so prescient, as all good science fiction should be, with its theme of bio-weapons meets corporate malfeasance, I credit the film a lot for violating the formerly pristine, white environments usually favored in depictions of space travel, through its spectacular focus on body horror. And this raises another intriguing question: whose sense of horror is it really? Perceptive critics have responded by examining the racial coding of the xenomorph as black, whereas feminists are fascinated and appalled in equal measure by the film's equating of technology and reproduction. I'd recommend reading this comparable essay on John Carpenter's The Thing for more of a sense of the "body horror" that might be at stake in Alien as well (The Thing, incidentally, shares with Alien a linkage back to the xenoarchaeological themes of Lovecraft's "At the Mountains of Madness"). Eric White ties together the issues of racial/species/gender identity in relation to evolutionary theory:
http://www.depauw.edu/sfs/backissues/61/white61art.htm
"After surveying the outer systems for many long years, a team finally made it back to Earth to find out why they had lost all contact. This pic was taken in China, but the team discovered identical statues in every major city around the world. The cities had all been reduced to smoking ruins and the atmosphere was no longer breathable. It seems Earth's fate had something to do with the mysterious Cthulhu cult which had spread during the team's absence...."
It isn't clear to me though whether the author's enthusiasms are really stopping short of the kind of Deleuzian excesses that we saw Steve Fuller recently criticizing in the interview I posted on this blog. Sci fi then can clearly be mobilized either in support of, or to express horror at, the kind of projects we humans strive for in the future. It can be worthwhile taking the time to seriously consider its implications.
Well, I guess until the new film comes out, I'll continue when I have moments to myself to take a relaxing walk, plotting my own little psychogeographies as I go by listening to and dreaming about certain music that for me evoke the scene of the crew approaching the derelict (such as the opening track of The Tower by Mordant Music). And speaking of artifacts, don't masks have a slightly xenoarchaeological quality about them as well, in that they too can function as gateways/portals in rituals and fantasy literature that can open the wearer up to forces with the power to transform personal identity? But as I've already hinted in my reference to Kane, to describe the "facehugger" in this way would be a bit of a stretch; although it was probably inevitable that someone would make this anyway (which is clever and humorous in its own way, to be sure).
These have just been a few fairly spontaneous musings inspired by my viewing of the new Prometheus trailer and then looking for a further excuse to avoid going back to work. Not long ago, for the very same reasons, I threw together the following little piece, which combines a couple of motifs from Alien and Lovecraft. It doesn't really look too bad on a big monitor. I thought the storyline could be something like this:
Monday, 21 November 2011
"...as if he's dousing bugs with insecticide"
Thanks for your excellent series of posts, derridata. I hope you're avoiding Spiked, which is running pathetic pieces comparing Occupy to the Tea Party!! Is Occupy the product of astroturfing funded by the Koch brothers? Uh, no, so there's really no comparison--but you'd never know that if you relied on Spiked.
Anyway, you've probably run across this latest atrocity, which reinforces the point of your post about paramilitary policing techniques:
"At the University of California at Davis this afternoon, police tore down down the tents of students inspired by the Occupy Wall Street movement, and arrested those who stood in their way. Others peacefully demanded that police release the arrested.
In the video, you see a police officer [Update: UC Davis Police Lt. John Pike] walk down a line of those young people seated quietly on the ground in an act of nonviolent civil disobedience, and spray them all with pepper spray at very close range. He is clearing a path for fellow officers to walk through and arrest more students, but it's as if he's dousing a row of bugs with insecticide.
Wayne Tilcock of the Davis-Enterprise newspaper has a gallery of photographs from the incident, including the image thumbnailed above (larger size at davisenterprise.com). Ten people in this scene were arrested, nine of whom were current UC Davis students. At least one woman is reported to have been taken away in an ambulance with chemical burns.
This 8-minute video was uploaded just a few hours ago, and has already become something of an iconic, viral emblem accross the web. We're flooded with eyewitness footage from OWS protests right now, but this one certainly feels like an important one, in part because of what the crowd does after the kids are pepper-sprayed. Watch the whole thing."
Sunday, 20 November 2011
Former Captain Ray Lewis Charged With Three Violations After Occupy Wall Street Protest
17th November: retired Philadelphia Police captain Ray Lewis was arrested at Occupy Wall Street. Lewis traveled to New York City to protest the heavy-handed behavior of the New York City Police Department.
Photo via Johnny Milano
Labels:
Johnny Milano,
NYPD,
Occupy Wall Street,
Police Brutality,
Ray Lewis
Saturday, 19 November 2011
Paramilitary Policing of Occupy Wall Street: Future Growth Industries
The paramilitary bureaucracy and the culture it engenders—a black-and-white world in which police unions serve above all to protect the brotherhood—is worse today than it was in the 1990s. Such agencies inevitably view protesters as the enemy. And young people, poor people and people of color will forever experience the institution as an abusive, militaristic force—not just during demonstrations but every day, in neighborhoods across the country.
Much of the problem is rooted in a rigid command-and-control hierarchy based on the military model. American police forces are beholden to archaic internal systems of authority whose rules emphasize bureaucratic regulations over conduct on the streets. An officer’s hair length, the shine on his shoes and the condition of his car are more important than whether he treats a burglary victim or a sex worker with dignity and respect. In the interest of 'discipline,' too many police bosses treat their frontline officers as dependent children, which helps explain why many of them behave more like juvenile delinquents than mature, competent professionals. It also helps to explain why persistent, patterned misconduct, including racism, sexism, homophobia, brutality, perjury and corruption, do not go away, no matter how many blue-ribbon panels are commissioned or how much training is provided.
Norm Stamper
former Seattle police chief and author of Breaking Rank: A Top Cop’s Exposé of the Dark Side of American Policing
Paramilitary Policing From Seattle to Occupy Wall Street
Friday, 18 November 2011
Monday, 14 November 2011
Why Occupy Wall Street? 4 Reasons.
My advice would be to avoid like the plague the kind of "analysis" offered in online forums such as Spiked! I don't think Frank Furedi has written anything insightful or fresh in the last ten years or so when examining social movements. He ALWAYS says their appeal is predicated merely on "moral authority". That criticism is so lazy because it merely obfuscates the differences between movements by refusing to engage with any concrete proposals on their own terms.
As an antidote, I recommend taking a look at the following video, which clearly sets out four reasons why Wall Street should be occupied. It also demonstrates the missed opportunities in the past when there was a chance to act in a pre-emptive fashion, and thereby avoid, or at least minimize, the catastrophe that has unfolded. Of course, regulation alone will never be a solution to the problems capitalism creates, but as a prelude to the "Great Emancipation", the social democratic reforms in the video have considerable merit.
Marx was a realist; the real romantics think you can have capitalism without great crisis:
As an antidote, I recommend taking a look at the following video, which clearly sets out four reasons why Wall Street should be occupied. It also demonstrates the missed opportunities in the past when there was a chance to act in a pre-emptive fashion, and thereby avoid, or at least minimize, the catastrophe that has unfolded. Of course, regulation alone will never be a solution to the problems capitalism creates, but as a prelude to the "Great Emancipation", the social democratic reforms in the video have considerable merit.
Marx was a realist; the real romantics think you can have capitalism without great crisis:
Saturday, 29 October 2011
The fascistic futurism of Ziggy Stardust
I was watching the Boyd Rice documentary Iconoclast last night, and was amazed by one scene where Rice showed a picture of Oswald Mosley addressing a rally of the British Union of Fascists. On either side of the stage was their distinctive "Flash and Circle" symbol ("England ignite!"), which Rice points out, David Bowie reused for his performances as Ziggy Stardust (not only having the symbol emblazoned across his face, but utilizing an identical arrangement of the symbols). Bowie has got away with this over the years, and was only ever really pulled up over his suspicious looking "Sieg Heil!" style salute captured in that infamous photo upon his arrival at Victoria Station, as well as his comment that, "Hitler was one of the first rock stars".
While the salute and comment might (almost) be explained away as spur of the moment provocations, Rice convincingly shows how consciously Bowie incorporated fascist iconography into his act. Oh wait, it's actually not correct to say he was only called to account for the Hitler comment and the salute, as Bowie is also on the record as having said, "Britain could benefit from a fascist leader" (see Buckley's bio of Bowie, Strange Fascination). I don't expect Bowie will ever fully, publicly, come clean--probably because he is now very embarrassed about this period of his career and regards such "statements" as morally abhorrent--so we have to thank Rice instead for alerting us to Ziggy's status as the first "(crypto) fascist alien" rock star. The example of Ziggy clearly proves that Bowie's fascist sympathies predated Station to Station.
British Union of Fascists rally at Earl's Court 1939 (click to enlarge to see symbols on either side of the stage and then compare to the pic [above] of the decorations behind Ziggy) |
Thursday, 27 October 2011
Welcome to the NHK
If you have this series on dvd Derridata, could you pl spin it my way at our next meeting? At this rate I'll have to sign up to Twitter! (lol!) Looks like just what I need when trying to also track down Richard Calder's Dead Girls i.e. obvious parallel themes of male protagonists falling victim to their technologically mediated consumption habits which are facilitated by a kind of "pornocracy" (c.f Videodrome).
And yes, of course, there is plenty of scope for feminist critique of Calder, as well as by queer theorists, who fault him for only considering the consequences for heterosexual characters (check the listed reference on Wikipedia). Notwithstanding such critical remarks, the process of being swallowed by this desire for consumption is interesting in terms of how Calder consciously draws parallels with vampirism (Rob Latham comments on this in his study of vampirism and the consumption of youth culture).
Returning to Welcome to NHK for the moment though, this next scene is an outrageous, surreal mixture of horror and humor, which might possibly be used to illustrate Kellner and Best's point that, "Paradoxically, today we find the atrophy of the senses in their hypertrophic extension throughout the sensorium of the spectacle and its images and commodity empires":
This "paradoxical effect" also seems comparable to the theme of vampirism Calder explores, as described by Latham.
In any case, Derridata, if you can find a way to incorporate this into one of your Japanese popular culture seminars, without violating copyright or offending community standards too much, please do so: it is guaranteed to generate a strong reaction from your students! Let me know if it eventuates, although I realise it's probably just wishful thinking on my part.
And yes, of course, there is plenty of scope for feminist critique of Calder, as well as by queer theorists, who fault him for only considering the consequences for heterosexual characters (check the listed reference on Wikipedia). Notwithstanding such critical remarks, the process of being swallowed by this desire for consumption is interesting in terms of how Calder consciously draws parallels with vampirism (Rob Latham comments on this in his study of vampirism and the consumption of youth culture).
Returning to Welcome to NHK for the moment though, this next scene is an outrageous, surreal mixture of horror and humor, which might possibly be used to illustrate Kellner and Best's point that, "Paradoxically, today we find the atrophy of the senses in their hypertrophic extension throughout the sensorium of the spectacle and its images and commodity empires":
This "paradoxical effect" also seems comparable to the theme of vampirism Calder explores, as described by Latham.
In any case, Derridata, if you can find a way to incorporate this into one of your Japanese popular culture seminars, without violating copyright or offending community standards too much, please do so: it is guaranteed to generate a strong reaction from your students! Let me know if it eventuates, although I realise it's probably just wishful thinking on my part.
Wednesday, 26 October 2011
Launch of Beta version of SFE: Science Fiction Encyclopedia
It launched on October 2. Absolutely essential reading
Saturday, 15 October 2011
Monday, 3 October 2011
Acheron Interview with Steve Fuller on "Humanity 2.0"
The following interview with Steve Fuller explores some of the issues raised by his new book, Humanity 2.0: What It Means to Be Human Past, Present and Future. For further background reading I recommend two other recent interviews with Steve in The Observer and Vice UK. A glance at Steve's schedule, including the RSA event featuring China Mieville (which this interview was also intended to help promote), shows that his commitment to this book is keeping him very busy indeed:
He will be speaking at the RSA on the 6th October:
http://www.thersa.org/events/our-events/humanity-2.0
And at Humanity Plus UK on the 8th October:
Beyond Human: Rethinking the Technological Extension of the Human Condition
You can also view chapter-by-chapter videos of Professor Steve Fuller talking about Humanity 2.0 here:
http://vimeo.com/channels/humanity2point0
...so I really must thank him for being so generous with his time by providing such detailed responses to my questions.
I must also thank Gregor Wolbring and Roger Griffin (Professor in Modern History at Oxford Brookes University) for responding to my requests by contributing a question each. Steve also wishes to express his appreciation for your respective contributions. And so now to the interview....
The popular market is filled with books by self-styled “futurists,” who are usually quick to adopt a technophile perspective, of whom Alvin Toffler and, more recently, Ray Kurzweil, are two of the most well-known examples. How can your approach be distinguished from that genre?
First, as someone who has been on the editorial board of the journal Futures for the past fifteen years, I suppose I am a ‘futurist’ of sorts. Certainly my views were canvassed in a recent survey of the epistemic horizons of leading futurists. Moreover, I am unapologetically normative, so I have no qualms about being called a ‘futurist’. After all, the future is the natural stomping ground of unrealised ideals. Indeed, I only object when futurists present themselves as pure describers, failing to acknowledge the forward momentum they give to the possible futures they deem likely – if they do not then go on to suggest ways in which those futures might be mitigated, diverted or reversed. In any case, all of this futurology is simply a secular extension of eschatology, an outgrowth of the prophetic religions, where ‘the point of it all’ is revealed. The scientific advance on this idea is to acknowledge both the fallibility and corrigibility of the piecemeal predictions we make along the way – and perhaps a recognition that whoever the deity may be, it needs humans to finish the job of creation. Humanity 2.0 is an account and defence of this line of thought.
A good way to see my starting point is by reading David Noble’s neglected classic The Religion of Technology: The Spirit of Invention and the Divinity of Man (1997). He clearly sees the seamless transition from medieval theology to modern technology – but only to condemn it. My Humanity 2.0 backs this view of history but gives it a somewhat more positive spin. To be sure, such an understanding of the human trajectory a mixed blessing, and my book aims to sharpen our sense of the costs and the benefits. All the talk in the book about ‘theodicy’ (the branch of theology devoted to the explanation of evil in a supposedly God-inspired world) is to do with this point. Toffler and Kurzweil don’t really acknowledge the costs of their techno-utopias (let alone who might bear those costs) or the groups – generically captured as ‘ecologists’ – who are prepared to resist them to the bitter end. These opponents are not scientific illiterates or technophobes but they still believe that humans need to live in some balance with nature. While in the past one might have associated these people with religiously inspired views (e.g. calling for our humility before the natural order), nowadays these people increasingly take to heart the Darwinian view that we are just one among many animal species with no special powers over the whole of reality. This is a remarkably defeatist view that, had it been taken seriously 400 years ago, would never have led to modern science.
As it turns out, I happen to think that history is on the side of the technophiles, but we shall need to play a long game. In particular, we need to overcome the idea of nature as a normative ideal once and for all. Appeals to ‘nature’ invariably aim to standardize for all times and places, often in the spirit of inhibiting humanity’s creative tendencies. This is something that the 18th century Enlightenment and the early 20th century ‘modernist’ movements understood very clearly in their attempts to valorise ‘artifice’ over ‘nature’. However, there are some tricky bits ahead, in particular how to reinvent the concept of ‘dignity’ in a world where humans regularly alter their own and others’ bodies. This concept, historically tied to the inviolability of ‘the human’ in natural law theory and lingers in today’s human rights legislation, has rested its intuitive appeal on a clear conception of the normal self-maintaining and self-determining human body. Not surprisingly, we nowadays find bioethicists, following the lead of the evolutionary psychologist Steven Pinker, trying to consign the concept of dignity to the dustbin of history. But that cannot be the final word on the matter. We need an ‘enhanced’ concept of dignity to create a normative boundary around the new and improved autonomous ‘human 2.0’, regardless of whether it is fully Homo sapiens.
Why did you decide to call the book Humanity 2.0? There have been some heated debates recently in response to the release of the movie Rise of the Planet of the Apes about whether we should feel obligated to "uplift" non-human animals as well. What’s your take then on the need for a Non-Human Animal 2.0?
To be honest, ‘Humanity 2.0’ began as a personal working title to keep me focused on the theme, given wide range of issues discussed in the book. But the publisher grew to like it for its marketing potential, and so there you have it. In the end, the full title – ‘Humanity 2.0: What It Means to Be Human Past, Present and Future’ – is an accurate description of the book’s contents. The book is not meant to be yet another mail order catalogue from the future written for today’s Geeks! More seriously, as I suggested in answer to the last question, the title Humanity 2.0 refers to the fact that our conception of the human is changing so that it need no longer involve the self-sufficiency of the biologically given human body, the traditional locus of the concept of ‘dignity’. However, from here we can go in two different directions, either or both of which could be ‘Humanity 2.0’ (There is an interesting policy question here about compatibility of the two alternatives, which I pick up again in the next question.)
On the one hand, we may head down the route of Peter Singer and adopt the normative standpoint of nature, which means setting standards of adequate living that have cross-species validity, such as the avoidance of pain, which would convert the value of human life as such from a constant to a variable, and hence open to manipulation and trade-off vis-à-vis the value of other life-forms. This is quite recognisable from ecologists and those who would curb (often militantly) the sacrifice of animals used to advance human medicine. On the other hand, there are those who would leave nature behind and identify their humanity with an existence outside their bodies – such as avatars in cyberspace. They are even willing to place their own biological lives and those of others at risk to be able to spend more quality time in a space where they feel they can really come into own. Throughout the book I stress that this option is legitimately seen as a secular continuation of the pursuit of a ‘spiritual’ existence, which has, generally speaking, taken our biological natures as a necessary evil – the more necessary, the more evil.
A clear transition point in the secularisation of the spiritual was Marx and Engels’ attitude towards capitalism as a waystation on the road to Communism. They clearly admired the efficiency generated by the Industrial Revolution, which held the potential to massively reduce the drudgery of labour, leaving time and space to pursue more ennobling activities that raised us above the animals. Of course, they objected to the social arrangements that inhibited this potential. But most interestingly, from the standpoint of Humanity 2.0, is the extent to which they and subsequent Marxists have promoted self-sacrifice and outright violence in pursuit of this aim – that is, they were definitely students of the ‘no pain, no gain’ school of progress, something that flies in the face of Singer’s global pain minimisation moral horizon. It would be interesting to see what Marx and Engels would make of the increasing technological mediation of human relations that mark our own times. Would they see it as a form of extended self-harm, à la Sherry Turkle or Susan Greenfield? Or, might they see it as the imposition of a new form of self-discipline, as in the original monastic orders? My guess is that the answer would turn on their assessment of the political economy governing cyberspace – and here I’d guess they would side with Evgeny Morozov of Net Delusion fame.
As for ‘Non-Human Animal 2.0’, I actually don’t believe that is implied by Rise of the Planet of the Apes. If anything, the new movie is very much in the spirit of my book in an important sense: It highlights the idea of the world becoming a ‘hominised substance’, to recall the phrase of the great heretical Jesuit palaeontologist Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, who is one of the heroes in Humanity 2.0. At first the apes are used as vehicles for testing a cure for Alzheimer’s disease but that allows them to develop intellectual capacities to outfox their human captors and eventually dominate the planet. Although the humans are ultimately vanquished for reasons not entirely related to the designs of the apes (i.e. a deadly virus that the ape’s blood transfers to humans), the plot is very transhumanist in that the means by which the conquest happens involves forms of intelligence that are very recognisably human: i.e., the ‘enhanced apes’ = how would humans respond if their minds were embodied in non-human primate bodies. It is a very non-Darwinian story of the future, since Darwin proposed a species egalitarian view of evolution, whereby any successor species to our own, while well adapted to its environment, may possess few of the qualities that we value in our own species.
By the way, this is why it’s always important to distinguish ‘posthumanism’ and ‘transhumanism’. The former simply refers to what historically comes after human dominion of the planet, regardless of whether humans are involved. In contrast, ‘transhumanism’ refers to the project of making the world more ‘human’ as a whole. I belong to the latter camp and so I am sympathetic to ideas floated intermittently from the Marquis de Condorcet to HG Wells and Buckminster Fuller of a ‘world brain’, as well as Teilhard de Chardin’s vision of evolution as a convergent process, whereby organisms coming from different biological starting points aim towards some ideal which so far Homo sapiens has achieved best but will be fully realized in some ‘omega’ moment in the future. I find it hard to entertain such an idea without presupposing a divine intelligence in the background as motivating the entire process. After all, the history of science and technology demonstrates the need for indefinite faith, tolerance and perseverance in order to endure the sacrifice and damage that have been done in pursuit of the so-called ‘heaven on earth’ we inhabit today. Most other cultures, including the Greeks and the Chinese, even when possessing many of the same guiding ideas, never took them with the West’s bloody-minded literalness. The best explanation is that we have believed those ideas to be divinely inspired, not simply passing fancies or clever tricks of limited application – and that belief has given us the requisite confidence, which has been empirically borne out over time. That ‘literalness’, by the way, is an outgrowth of first Franciscan and then Calvinist attitudes to the Bible, which by the modern period gave writing in general (as our expression of God’s creative logos) an unprecedented power to authorise the exact governance of society and the world at large. John Milton’s classic defence of freedom of the press, Areopagitica, is very good on this close connection between the divinity of written expression and the capacity for self-governance.
Can the book be usefully contextualized in relation to “technoprogressivism,” which Wikipedia defines as: “…a stance of active support for the convergence of technological change and social change. Techno-progressives argue that technological developments can be profoundly empowering and emancipatory when they are regulated by legitimate democratic and accountable authorities to ensure that their costs, risks and benefits are all fairly shared by the actual stakeholders to those developments.” To me, that pretty much describes the mandate of the social epistemology which you have developed over many years. Would you assent to a characterization of Humanity 2.0 then as a kind of technoprogressivist manifesto? (*note: interested readers might like to test the extent of their own “techno tolerance” by completing this short quiz)
Yes, except with the proviso that we’re entering into a period when who counts as part of the ‘we’ engaged in this project of collective self-improvement is open to serious re-negotiation. The Royal Society of Arts in London has agreed to launch my book with a conference on 6th October that is being prompted by a blogpost where I take the issue head-on by considering what our National Health Service might look like, if we included elected animals and androids, alongside humans, amongst those under its coverage – keeping in mind the current regime of fiscal austerity, in which adding new entities de facto means eliminating others, unless some more creative solution is on offer (e.g. merging of individual identities into some more borg-like entity: a more Star Trek view of ‘empowerment’). Let me say that on this issue, Peter Singer’s hard-nosed utilitarianism with its open discussion of costs, benefits and trade-offs for individual lives in relation to an overall social welfare function is right on the money. (Too bad he fetishises carbon-based entities!) In contrast, I find the ‘irreductionist’ crowd surrounding Bruno Latour and other ontological inflationists (aka ‘speculative realists’) as simply dodging this normative bullet and rendering themselves irrelevant to the emerging political economy debates. I realize that part of their own normative position is to complicate the world with agents to render their own interpretive services necessary but these might be usefully employed elsewhere.
One of the most distinct features of your position when compared with the self-described technoprogressives though appears to be your emphasis—albeit without using this specific term—on afflatus: i.e. the sense that science has historically being reliant on a sense of divine inspiration to help rally others behind its cause. I can see how this could be advantageous in technoprogressivist terms when it comes to ensuring that “risks and benefits are all fairly shared.” It surprises me though when even an evolutionary biologist such as David Sloan Wilson (see his Darwin’s Cathedral) is willing to refer to sociologists, such as Durkheim and Rodney Stark, to bolster a (at first glance) similar argument about how the purpose of religion is to unite human groups. It seems then that some might be happy to think that this is because of our status as adaptive organisms, while others (such as most technoprogressives, apparently) prefer to rally around democratic norms, without feeling any need to dress them up in religious garb. Some sociologists might use the Thomas theorem, or, what basically amounts to the same thing, Robert K Merton’s “Matthew Effect,” to frame these respective preferences as examples of a self-fulfilling prophecy—i.e. if people define a situation as real, it will be real in its consequences. I can see some benefits of this pragmatic stance as far as facilitating the kind of broad coalition-building upon which democratic politics depends is concerned; at least when understood as “the art of the possible.” I sense though that this kind of approach falls well short of the kind of social constructivism you prefer, right?
You raise a couple of interesting points here. First, on the role of religion as human motivator: The world-religions really divide on this point. The great non-Abrahamic religions of the East, the so-called the ‘wisdom religions’ (Hinduism, Buddhism, Confucianism, Taoism), do indeed orient people in ways that might fit a story of evolutionary adaptation, since they aim to get people to reach equilibrium with their environment, typically with minimum force applied to those concerned. In contrast, the Abrahamic religions are all about living up to God’s standards, which invariably means a radical transformation of ourselves and our world; hence, the great stress that especially Christianity and Islam place on deciding to believe –i.e. drawing a line on your past life and embarking upon a new one fully of uncertainties yet no less purposeful for that. This empowering sense of religion is not easily explained in evolutionary terms because it calls for us to continually de-stabilise our default mode of being, most notably by developing moral commitments to those outside our immediate family and community, which would otherwise be the locus of concern dictated by the Darwinian logic of survival.
This brings us to the second point: While it is certainly fair to describe the Abrahamic concern for a ‘universal humanity’ to be ‘artificial’ as opposed to ‘natural’ (which explains the need to enshrine this concern as an explicit code of conduct), the ‘social constructions’ one subsequently engages in do not necessarily bear fruit immediately or even directly. In that respect, the pragmatic payoff of living, say, a Christian life is typically not realized in proportion to the effort put in -- that’s one operational way of defining reality as ‘independent’ of us. Indeed, as in the case of Calvinists, the benefits may be deferred for one’s entire biological life, only to be redeemed in the afterlife. As I suggested in answer to the previous question, the history of science and technology in the modern period partakes of this mode of thought, so we continue remaking the world in our image and likeness, always presuming that the benefits outweigh the costs, even as the columns of the our collective existential balance sheet mount up differently. Recalling Karl Popper’s famous distinction in The Poverty of Historicism (1957) between ‘prediction’ and ‘prophecy’ as a rough-and-ready way of distinguishing science from religion, I would stress that our commitment to science itself (as opposed to its particular theories) is in the mode of a prophetic religion. Indeed, Popper would be in agreement, since he believed that the faith-based nature of science was demonstrated by our belief that we could reach the truth – as opposed to a sceptical dead end -- by engaging in the resolute elimination of error
Ok, that explains why you think we need a Religion 2.0 to complement the conception of Humanity 2.0. I notice that one of your co-panellists in the discussion on Humanity 2.0 to be held at the RSA on October 6th is the renowned fantasy fiction author, committed socialist, and atheist, China Miéville. I expect Miéville will go out of his way to emphasise (what he would most likely regard as) the inherent limitations of any reliance on liberal democratic institutions in the face of the powerful logics of commodification driving the technoscience behind genetics, nanotechnology, and robotics. Unequivocal arguments along these lines have also been issued by critical theorists such as Frédéric Vandenberghe and Glenn Rikowski.
I only mention these points because on page 215 you write: “Marxism as the putative ‘no discount zone’ failed because, in the end, the labour theory of value provided at most a regulative ideal towards which an existing society might aim but little guidance in either identifying or redressing ‘differences that make a difference’ in such a society. In this respect, Marxism lacked a distinctly sociological sensibility, which is perhaps most evident in the movement’s eschatological impulse to end history formally and create society anew.” You then go on to give a positive account of the tax system as a social democratic solution for “administering justice across classes and generations.” What is the intended take-home message for Marxists here? Should the book be understood as providing this needed “sociological sensibility” to Marxist critiques of transhumanism etc, or is it implying that the best we can probably hope for in the future is managed affluence—meaning that piecemeal reforms are the most realistic means of curbing the excesses of what you refer to as “bioliberalism”?
First, I must confess that I do not follow the Deleuzians as closely as others do, but I notice that they do tend toward the mealy-mouthed when dealing with Humanity 2.0. Really now, what is this backhanded ‘let’s hope for a post-human that’s not inhuman’? Why not call it by its proper name and fight for it: ‘transhumanism’? We should be about promoting as widely as possible the aspects of our being that we find most admirable and take collective responsibility for the consequences. Of course, the political implications of this idea are far from obvious and are bound to be controversial. Still, the transhumanists start the argument the right way round – instead of looking at the world as we find it and then expressing our disappointments, regrets and fears in ever so artful ways, which seems to be the Deleuzian policy, as they simply take the animal side of the argument as given. In this I am very much with the Fichtean idealist roots of Marxism, with its proactive stance towards the intelligently guided human will.
Where Marxism has faltered – and interestingly my criticism applies more to Marx’s so-called ‘humanist’ early work than his later more ‘scientistic’ phase – has been in its essentialism towards our ‘species being’, which is ever on the lookout for the negative consequences of alienation but seemingly blind to the positive consequences of having a legally protected sphere of free exchange. In this respect, Marx continued down the path of Rousseau beyond the point that Kant got off. Because Kant does not identify our unique potential for autonomy with the sheer possession of a human body, he lacks Marx’s fastidiousness over whether individuals are selling their birth right by acceding to substandard work conditions. For Kant, what matters is the state of mind in which such a decision is taken, not the impact that the decision might have on the future condition of the body. If I were of a more panglossian frame of mind, I would be tempted to say that capitalism has actually helped people to think about their humanity more sharply by forcing them continually rethink what is essential and accidental in terms of the sort of being that they aspire to be, since any advancement will invariably involve selling some part of oneself.
The problem I raise about Marxism’s ‘sociological deficit’, so to speak, relates to the sharp disjunction, even schizophrenia, in the Marxist literature between the Communist ideal of human equality, understood as a state of universal emancipation, and whatever means it might take – be they parliamentary or revolutionary -- to reach it. For a political movement that is officially committed to ‘the unity of theory and practice’, Marxism has had a long and embarrassing tendency of not owning up to the history of its own practice, a point that eventually led Popper to revoke Marxism’s scientific credentials. Marxist theorists routinely distance themselves from both the peaceful and violent sides of that history, as ‘failures of the revolution’: Social democrats are co-opted wimps, and totalitarians over-the-top monsters. Against this backdrop, one comes to appreciate the distinctiveness of Lenin who clearly wanted to honour both Marx’s philosophical integrity and political animus in his own practice. But of course this meant killing people when they got in the way of the dialectic. I talk about ‘theodicy’ in this context as well. While Marx himself would have known that Hegel got his ironic view of world-history from Leibniz’s theodicy, his followers have been reluctant to admit the full force of this lineage, which entails accepting that people will have to suffer before they become better.
One of the most vocal advocates of “democratic transhumanism” is James Hughes (author of Citizen Cyborg). In an article entitled “The Politics of Transhumanism,” Hughes worryingly refers to a small group of neo-Nazis who have attached themselves to the movement. This might be an ideal segue-way for Roger Griffin, who sent the following response:
ROGER GRIFFIN: I do not wish to comment on the book as a whole. I notice, however, several passages that refer to the ongoing historical significance of the Third Reich with respect to how scientific developments might be harnessed to a progressive future. For the sake of brevity, I will confine my remarks to the following passage, which appears on page 244:
"Albeit often in defence of odious policies, this strand of the American political tradition has consistently upheld the legitimacy of social action taken by self-organising individuals. Can such a story be told even for Nazi Germany, in spite of the enormity of the suffering it caused? If we wish to continue including the Nazis as part of the history of humanity – as opposed to the history of nature – then the answer must be yes, however difficult at first glance that may seem. Put bluntly, we must envisage the prospect of a transformation in the normative image of Nazi Germany comparable to what Barrington Moore described for the French Revolution. This is not easy. The makeover Moore observed occurred over a couple of generations, and in that same amount of time there have been only the barest hints of Nazi rehabilitation. But hints there are, helped along by the death of those with first-hand experience of Nazism. To be sure, some areas of Nazi science that did not figure prominently in the Second World War – such as space travel, ecology and cancer research – were easily, if somewhat surreptitiously, assimilated by the Allies. But even in the case of the Nazi science of ‘racial hygiene’, there is a dawning realisation that ‘eugenics’ and ‘genetic modification’ more generally have been always integral to progressive normative agendas. In that case Nazi science policies are perhaps best seen as opportunistically extreme versions of tendencies long present and accepted by the intellectual vanguard of Western culture. Lest this speculation seem, once again, too panglossian, it is worth noting that Nazi Germany promoted itself in just this way – with considerable success in the international media – before the presentation of evidence for the Holocaust. If one is inclined to think, as I am, that the Holocaust was produced by the exigencies of war rather than intrinsic to the Nazi agenda, then a key to recovering the ‘good’ in Nazism might be to rewind history to the 1920s and 1930s when the movement appeared to offer the promise of a progressive future. Back then the Holocaust did not appear to be an inevitable outcome of Nazism, which in turn enabled observers to see Nazis as fruitfully extending existing scientific agendas" (cf. Fuller 2006b: chap. 14).
This is a curious passage: historians have long been working on integrating Nazism within human history rather than demonizing it simply as ‘evil’ or ‘barbaric’ or ‘monstrous’. A whole industry of sophisticated Third Reich history exists, prominent representatives of which writing in English are Richard Evans, Michael Burleigh, and Ian Kershaw. So Nazism is already an integral part of human history.
But rehabilitating Nazism, Stalinism, the Pol Pot regime etc is quite another issue. Germans have been rehabilitated and reaccepted into the fold of civilized humanity, but somehow accommodating Hitler’s regime as a positive episode of human history is simply perverse. It sounds as if the author wants to cherry pick aspects of Nazism which are somehow ‘progressive’ in order to graft Nazism back into the Western scheme of ‘progress’. This would be a deeply mythic exercise which has a lot to do with how ‘the general public’, ‘collective consciousness’ digests human atrocities (First World War, WW2, 9/11) or forgets them (US genocide in North America, the Slave Trade etc). Digesting them reminds me of how a snake eats a dog, namely by dislocating its jaw.
Who is the ‘we’ that must envisage a transformation of the normative image of the Third Reich? Historiography is not about normalizing but understanding. Cancer research is not about normalizing cancer but understanding its mechanisms.
Unsurprisingly then, I disagree with the claim that eugenics has ‘always been integral to progressive normative agendas’. Eugenics grew up in the 19th century and in its ‘positive’ but non-coercive concern with health has been embraced within enlightened social policies the world over. But the negative eugenics of the sort that sterilizes and kills which lay at the heart of Nazi social engineering has been utterly discredited as a perverse, deeply irrational ideology which acquired the deeply pathological momentum of a crusade against decadence for some believers in science as a substitute religion on which to base a healthy society and had long been rejected by humanists.
I also have considerable reservations about the claim that the Nazi eugenic campaign was due to the exigencies of war because it borders dangerously on revisionist history (e.g. of someone like Ernst Nolte) which rehabilitates Nazism by using a range of arguments that rework the facts. The works of Browning and Kershaw offer a great deal of historical evidence to undermine any relationship between the exigencies of war and the Holocaust.
The historical fact is that the Nazi war on communism, democracy and what were deemed ideological and racial enemies was integral to the whole being and purpose of the Nazi revolution, the premise for the construction of a new order and a new Nazi empire purged of undesirable elements/filth. Auschwitz was called “the anus of Europe” by the Nazis because it excreted Jews, and the genocide continued to the last days of the war long after the exigencies of war had stopped.
My concern is that the revisionist thrust of this passage is basically scrambling the valid point that Nazism is an integral chapter of the history of modernity (which does NOT mean something intrinsically good). I hope the author might consider a close reading of Bauman’s The Holocaust and Modernity (and even my Modernism and Fascism) as a corrective.
In sum, I would strongly argue that there was no 'good' in Nazism because (from a non-Nazi perspective) all the good was at the expense of bad (persecution, torture, the destruction of lives, genocide etc) and this ‘bad’ was integral to the ‘good’. It is possible to imagine counterfactually a French Revolution without the Terror and even a Russian Revolution and a Maoist Revolution that did not cause scores of millions of deaths and create vast systems of prison camps and oceans of suffering (just): but the revolutions undertaken by Hitler and Pol Pot were destined in their very conception to mass produce atrocities, and there can be no ‘rehabilitation’ of a regime that does this, just de-demonization by humanistic historians interested in making sense of history rather than trying to cling desperately onto the mast of the Ship of Enlightenment as it is battered by the waves of the ‘storm of progress’.
This is a very interesting and perhaps telling line of inquiry. Roger is certainly right that I disagree with Bauman’s The Holocaust and Modernity (I briefly critiqued it in The New Sociological Imagination but merely ignore it in Humanity 2.0), and we certainly disagree about the role of eugenics in the history of progressive politics – which is something I raise not only at the end of Humanity 2.0 (as noted by Roger) but throughout the book, especially chapter one, where I note the generally strong support for eugenics on the part of the Fabian socialists who were behind the funding of the UK’s first sociology chair, at the London School of Economics in 1907. This was no fluke but quite consistent with the biopolitics surrounding the establishment of welfare states throughout Europe. It’s no accident that eugenics originated with a self-identified progressive, Francis Galton, and his work was translated into German by Otto Neurath, then a young socialist associated with the Vienna Circle (i.e. not some disgruntled racist Junker). Moreover, the political economist William Beveridge, while LSE director, and just before he created the British welfare state, got the Rockefeller Foundation to fund a chair in ‘social biology’ that would operate as both a mass data gatherer of vital statistics of the body politic and a theoretical foundation for the social sciences. This move proved unpopular and ultimately failed, but for reasons unrelated to matters of genocide. A book due out next year by a young historian (for which I wrote the Foreword) goes through this history quite carefully, in an attempt to explain why British sociology so thoroughly turned its back on biology, even though the country was seen as very much in the vanguard at the dawn of the 20th century: Chris Renwick, British Sociology’s Lost Biological Roots (Palgrave Macmillan, 2012).
Once we set aside the assumption that the Holocaust is a necessary consequence or ultimate expression of eugenics – in other words, once we refuse to let our current moral response to the Holocaust colour our understanding of all the preceding relevant history – it should be pretty clear that eugenics was a left-wing project, both in its ‘negative’ and ‘positive’ forms. I don’t deny that people were sterilised without their consent or appropriate legal representation. To be sure, this is very much to be regretted. However, given the routine violation of human dignity that has attended the history of scientific medicine more generally, I doubt that those episodes alone would have warranted the censoriousness with which people like Roger regard eugenics. Clearly the Holocaust is driving his understanding of an entire scientific project that had promised a gradual, collective, empirically monitored and politically accountable upgrading of the human condition. This is precisely what attracted the Fabians (whose name comes from the Roman general who beat Hannibal by not acting impulsively). While virtually all social reformers of the late 19th and early 20th centuries were calling for greater education and improvement of living conditions as vehicles of social transformation, there was also a general recognition that people with right capacities were also needed to make maximum use of those opportunities, understood as choices that such people could make for themselves without excessive state intervention. In short, the eugenicists committed themselves to building a society whose members were ‘fit to be free’, you might say. Ideologically speaking, I see this project as treating the human gene pool as collectively owned property, whose state-managed cultivation aims to produce people capable of flourishing in a liberal society. You may find this vision heroic or scary or both, but I believe that developments across the sciences and technologies increasingly beckon us to revive this project in a new key, ‘Eugenics 2.0’, if you will. ‘Transhumanism’, a coinage of the eugenicist Julian Huxley, is one of the popular labels under which it nowadays travels. Put that way, humans are clearly claiming some of (the Abrahamic) God’s powers for themselves. But in the early 21st century this should be no cause for alarm. After all, modernity has been all about prior sacrileges being upgraded into the sincerest form of flattery to the deity.
As for my wishing to ‘rehabilitate’ Nazism, yes, in the sense that their activities come to be understood as having served larger goals that in the long run have benefited humanity—in particular, by testing the limits of our knowledge and being. ‘National socialism’ was commonly used for the nation-based welfare states of Scandinavia that inspired Hitler. This was to do with the accuracy of the phrase, especially in contradistinction to a Trotsky-style free-floating World Communist movement that denied the possibility of socialism in one country. We need to put our understanding of Nazism back into that context. I am not trying to rewrite Nazi motives, but write them more completely -- and I freely admit that their motives became corrupt by the time of the Holocaust. My aim is to broaden the context for assessing the consequences of Nazi actions, something very much in the spirit of ‘theodicy’, that is, God’s sense of justice. It involves treating every act – however prima facie noble or ignoble – as ultimately no more and no less than a means to a more exalted end, namely, completion of the divine plan, in which we are the principal agent. This is the moral horizon of Humanity 2.0. At the very least, it allows us to get the most mileage out of the Nazi experience – which, like it or not, we’re stuck with -- by refusing to set up artificial barriers to our treating it charitably, perhaps in the spirit of ‘it was a dirty job, but someone had to do it’. Indeed, maybe the Nazis reveal that even God must operate with dirty hands.
My inclination to forgive is not as crazy as it may sound. Indeed, the memory of the Holocaust is nowadays kept alive by a kind of suspended animation of historical consciousness that prevents it from being properly integrated into our collective psyche. Recall that the Arab-Israeli War of 1967, which resulted in Israel’s deeply unpopular redrawing of its territorial boundaries, unleashed what Peter Novick and Norman Finkelstein have provocatively described as the ‘Holocaust Industry’, namely, a concerted effort to ensure that the Holocaust’s enormity was never forgotten. This project, which continues to engage some of social theory’s most sophisticated minds, is admitted by all sides to be an uphill struggle, since our default collective psychology is to forget, if not exactly forgive. To be sure, I don’t believe in forgetting Nazi atrocities. On the contrary, I believe that they remain pedagogically useful for illustrating what it means to realize long-held scientific desires with impunity and from which we now continue to benefit, even though we cannot see ourselves as having committed the original acts involved. But in the final analysis, the apparent moral and epistemic certitude with which Roger expresses his views leads me to two conclusions: (1) even today the history of science has yet to be properly integrated into the history of modernity; (2) our understanding of the causes and significance of the Holocaust is still very much distorted by a preoccupation with its most abnormal and abhorrent aspects – as if simply creating moral distance from the Holocaust were sufficient to establish our own superiority.
GREGOR WOLBRING: How can we mainstream ableism studies into academic and public discourses given that this lens gives us a fresh clue on dynamics and consequences?
According to ‘ableism’, the mark – if not stigmata – of the transhuman condition is that everyone, not just the conventionally disabled, will come to feel ‘always already’ disabled. This is because the increasing demand – and ultimately supply – or bio-enhancements will cause the standards of normative performance to shift upward. In effect, ‘being normal’ itself becomes what welfare economists call a ‘positional good’, which is to say, its value is tied to its relative scarcity: Thus, the value of being clever lies in being cleverer than others. The great virtue of ableism is that it places the questions surrounding our biotechnological enhancement squarely in the realm of political economy, very much as Francis Galton and William Beveridge thought about eugenics. Thus, contrary to the popular rhetoric of tranhumanist enthusiasts, transhumanist desires are not simply free-floating ideals or freely chosen identities, but emergent features of a fluid political and scientific situation concerning our future.
Gregor asks about how to make ableism studies ‘mainstream’. My general answer to ‘mainstreaming’ questions is to provide an adequate backstory in our common intellectual and cultural history. Like any recently identified movement, ‘ableism’ suffers from ‘the shock of the new’, which in turn instinctively inclines people to respond to it as alien, if not outright threatening. Ableism may be especially prone to this treatment because of the deep challenges it poses to how we define ‘normal’ and ‘disabled’ bodies. However, in Humanity 2.0, I observe that the hopes and anxieties generated by an ableist mentality is traceable to a semantic innovation of the fourteenth century Oxford Franciscan, John Duns Scotus, in discussing God’s properties. Scotus basically detached each of the divine properties from the deity so as to analyse each of them as independent capabilities that are developed finitely in humans but infinitely in God. For example, from the idea of ‘all-powerful father’ was derived the idea of ‘power’ as such as a dimension in terms of which God indefinitely surpasses us. Moreover, Scotus suggested that in humans all of these potentially divine dimensions are developed to varying degrees, and of course none to anything approaching the divine limit. While it may be easy to say that God is all-powerful, all-loving and all-knowing, just based on the range of humans that history has put on offer, it is difficult to imagine the sort of being in whom all those capabilities would be developed to such a great extent. Indeed, a major source of human misery is the uneven development of such capabilities within ourselves, whereby we are overdeveloped in some and underdeveloped in others. Ableism provides a high-tech secular way of revisiting those ontological concerns of the High Middle Ages.
Is there anything you'd like to add?
As my response to the several of the questions here indicate, proceeding to ‘Humanity 2.0’ requires a re-engagement with Western theology on at least three nowadays neglected fronts:
The popular market is filled with books by self-styled “futurists,” who are usually quick to adopt a technophile perspective, of whom Alvin Toffler and, more recently, Ray Kurzweil, are two of the most well-known examples. How can your approach be distinguished from that genre?
First, as someone who has been on the editorial board of the journal Futures for the past fifteen years, I suppose I am a ‘futurist’ of sorts. Certainly my views were canvassed in a recent survey of the epistemic horizons of leading futurists. Moreover, I am unapologetically normative, so I have no qualms about being called a ‘futurist’. After all, the future is the natural stomping ground of unrealised ideals. Indeed, I only object when futurists present themselves as pure describers, failing to acknowledge the forward momentum they give to the possible futures they deem likely – if they do not then go on to suggest ways in which those futures might be mitigated, diverted or reversed. In any case, all of this futurology is simply a secular extension of eschatology, an outgrowth of the prophetic religions, where ‘the point of it all’ is revealed. The scientific advance on this idea is to acknowledge both the fallibility and corrigibility of the piecemeal predictions we make along the way – and perhaps a recognition that whoever the deity may be, it needs humans to finish the job of creation. Humanity 2.0 is an account and defence of this line of thought.
A good way to see my starting point is by reading David Noble’s neglected classic The Religion of Technology: The Spirit of Invention and the Divinity of Man (1997). He clearly sees the seamless transition from medieval theology to modern technology – but only to condemn it. My Humanity 2.0 backs this view of history but gives it a somewhat more positive spin. To be sure, such an understanding of the human trajectory a mixed blessing, and my book aims to sharpen our sense of the costs and the benefits. All the talk in the book about ‘theodicy’ (the branch of theology devoted to the explanation of evil in a supposedly God-inspired world) is to do with this point. Toffler and Kurzweil don’t really acknowledge the costs of their techno-utopias (let alone who might bear those costs) or the groups – generically captured as ‘ecologists’ – who are prepared to resist them to the bitter end. These opponents are not scientific illiterates or technophobes but they still believe that humans need to live in some balance with nature. While in the past one might have associated these people with religiously inspired views (e.g. calling for our humility before the natural order), nowadays these people increasingly take to heart the Darwinian view that we are just one among many animal species with no special powers over the whole of reality. This is a remarkably defeatist view that, had it been taken seriously 400 years ago, would never have led to modern science.
As it turns out, I happen to think that history is on the side of the technophiles, but we shall need to play a long game. In particular, we need to overcome the idea of nature as a normative ideal once and for all. Appeals to ‘nature’ invariably aim to standardize for all times and places, often in the spirit of inhibiting humanity’s creative tendencies. This is something that the 18th century Enlightenment and the early 20th century ‘modernist’ movements understood very clearly in their attempts to valorise ‘artifice’ over ‘nature’. However, there are some tricky bits ahead, in particular how to reinvent the concept of ‘dignity’ in a world where humans regularly alter their own and others’ bodies. This concept, historically tied to the inviolability of ‘the human’ in natural law theory and lingers in today’s human rights legislation, has rested its intuitive appeal on a clear conception of the normal self-maintaining and self-determining human body. Not surprisingly, we nowadays find bioethicists, following the lead of the evolutionary psychologist Steven Pinker, trying to consign the concept of dignity to the dustbin of history. But that cannot be the final word on the matter. We need an ‘enhanced’ concept of dignity to create a normative boundary around the new and improved autonomous ‘human 2.0’, regardless of whether it is fully Homo sapiens.
Why did you decide to call the book Humanity 2.0? There have been some heated debates recently in response to the release of the movie Rise of the Planet of the Apes about whether we should feel obligated to "uplift" non-human animals as well. What’s your take then on the need for a Non-Human Animal 2.0?
To be honest, ‘Humanity 2.0’ began as a personal working title to keep me focused on the theme, given wide range of issues discussed in the book. But the publisher grew to like it for its marketing potential, and so there you have it. In the end, the full title – ‘Humanity 2.0: What It Means to Be Human Past, Present and Future’ – is an accurate description of the book’s contents. The book is not meant to be yet another mail order catalogue from the future written for today’s Geeks! More seriously, as I suggested in answer to the last question, the title Humanity 2.0 refers to the fact that our conception of the human is changing so that it need no longer involve the self-sufficiency of the biologically given human body, the traditional locus of the concept of ‘dignity’. However, from here we can go in two different directions, either or both of which could be ‘Humanity 2.0’ (There is an interesting policy question here about compatibility of the two alternatives, which I pick up again in the next question.)
On the one hand, we may head down the route of Peter Singer and adopt the normative standpoint of nature, which means setting standards of adequate living that have cross-species validity, such as the avoidance of pain, which would convert the value of human life as such from a constant to a variable, and hence open to manipulation and trade-off vis-à-vis the value of other life-forms. This is quite recognisable from ecologists and those who would curb (often militantly) the sacrifice of animals used to advance human medicine. On the other hand, there are those who would leave nature behind and identify their humanity with an existence outside their bodies – such as avatars in cyberspace. They are even willing to place their own biological lives and those of others at risk to be able to spend more quality time in a space where they feel they can really come into own. Throughout the book I stress that this option is legitimately seen as a secular continuation of the pursuit of a ‘spiritual’ existence, which has, generally speaking, taken our biological natures as a necessary evil – the more necessary, the more evil.
A clear transition point in the secularisation of the spiritual was Marx and Engels’ attitude towards capitalism as a waystation on the road to Communism. They clearly admired the efficiency generated by the Industrial Revolution, which held the potential to massively reduce the drudgery of labour, leaving time and space to pursue more ennobling activities that raised us above the animals. Of course, they objected to the social arrangements that inhibited this potential. But most interestingly, from the standpoint of Humanity 2.0, is the extent to which they and subsequent Marxists have promoted self-sacrifice and outright violence in pursuit of this aim – that is, they were definitely students of the ‘no pain, no gain’ school of progress, something that flies in the face of Singer’s global pain minimisation moral horizon. It would be interesting to see what Marx and Engels would make of the increasing technological mediation of human relations that mark our own times. Would they see it as a form of extended self-harm, à la Sherry Turkle or Susan Greenfield? Or, might they see it as the imposition of a new form of self-discipline, as in the original monastic orders? My guess is that the answer would turn on their assessment of the political economy governing cyberspace – and here I’d guess they would side with Evgeny Morozov of Net Delusion fame.
As for ‘Non-Human Animal 2.0’, I actually don’t believe that is implied by Rise of the Planet of the Apes. If anything, the new movie is very much in the spirit of my book in an important sense: It highlights the idea of the world becoming a ‘hominised substance’, to recall the phrase of the great heretical Jesuit palaeontologist Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, who is one of the heroes in Humanity 2.0. At first the apes are used as vehicles for testing a cure for Alzheimer’s disease but that allows them to develop intellectual capacities to outfox their human captors and eventually dominate the planet. Although the humans are ultimately vanquished for reasons not entirely related to the designs of the apes (i.e. a deadly virus that the ape’s blood transfers to humans), the plot is very transhumanist in that the means by which the conquest happens involves forms of intelligence that are very recognisably human: i.e., the ‘enhanced apes’ = how would humans respond if their minds were embodied in non-human primate bodies. It is a very non-Darwinian story of the future, since Darwin proposed a species egalitarian view of evolution, whereby any successor species to our own, while well adapted to its environment, may possess few of the qualities that we value in our own species.
By the way, this is why it’s always important to distinguish ‘posthumanism’ and ‘transhumanism’. The former simply refers to what historically comes after human dominion of the planet, regardless of whether humans are involved. In contrast, ‘transhumanism’ refers to the project of making the world more ‘human’ as a whole. I belong to the latter camp and so I am sympathetic to ideas floated intermittently from the Marquis de Condorcet to HG Wells and Buckminster Fuller of a ‘world brain’, as well as Teilhard de Chardin’s vision of evolution as a convergent process, whereby organisms coming from different biological starting points aim towards some ideal which so far Homo sapiens has achieved best but will be fully realized in some ‘omega’ moment in the future. I find it hard to entertain such an idea without presupposing a divine intelligence in the background as motivating the entire process. After all, the history of science and technology demonstrates the need for indefinite faith, tolerance and perseverance in order to endure the sacrifice and damage that have been done in pursuit of the so-called ‘heaven on earth’ we inhabit today. Most other cultures, including the Greeks and the Chinese, even when possessing many of the same guiding ideas, never took them with the West’s bloody-minded literalness. The best explanation is that we have believed those ideas to be divinely inspired, not simply passing fancies or clever tricks of limited application – and that belief has given us the requisite confidence, which has been empirically borne out over time. That ‘literalness’, by the way, is an outgrowth of first Franciscan and then Calvinist attitudes to the Bible, which by the modern period gave writing in general (as our expression of God’s creative logos) an unprecedented power to authorise the exact governance of society and the world at large. John Milton’s classic defence of freedom of the press, Areopagitica, is very good on this close connection between the divinity of written expression and the capacity for self-governance.
Can the book be usefully contextualized in relation to “technoprogressivism,” which Wikipedia defines as: “…a stance of active support for the convergence of technological change and social change. Techno-progressives argue that technological developments can be profoundly empowering and emancipatory when they are regulated by legitimate democratic and accountable authorities to ensure that their costs, risks and benefits are all fairly shared by the actual stakeholders to those developments.” To me, that pretty much describes the mandate of the social epistemology which you have developed over many years. Would you assent to a characterization of Humanity 2.0 then as a kind of technoprogressivist manifesto? (*note: interested readers might like to test the extent of their own “techno tolerance” by completing this short quiz)
Yes, except with the proviso that we’re entering into a period when who counts as part of the ‘we’ engaged in this project of collective self-improvement is open to serious re-negotiation. The Royal Society of Arts in London has agreed to launch my book with a conference on 6th October that is being prompted by a blogpost where I take the issue head-on by considering what our National Health Service might look like, if we included elected animals and androids, alongside humans, amongst those under its coverage – keeping in mind the current regime of fiscal austerity, in which adding new entities de facto means eliminating others, unless some more creative solution is on offer (e.g. merging of individual identities into some more borg-like entity: a more Star Trek view of ‘empowerment’). Let me say that on this issue, Peter Singer’s hard-nosed utilitarianism with its open discussion of costs, benefits and trade-offs for individual lives in relation to an overall social welfare function is right on the money. (Too bad he fetishises carbon-based entities!) In contrast, I find the ‘irreductionist’ crowd surrounding Bruno Latour and other ontological inflationists (aka ‘speculative realists’) as simply dodging this normative bullet and rendering themselves irrelevant to the emerging political economy debates. I realize that part of their own normative position is to complicate the world with agents to render their own interpretive services necessary but these might be usefully employed elsewhere.
One of the most distinct features of your position when compared with the self-described technoprogressives though appears to be your emphasis—albeit without using this specific term—on afflatus: i.e. the sense that science has historically being reliant on a sense of divine inspiration to help rally others behind its cause. I can see how this could be advantageous in technoprogressivist terms when it comes to ensuring that “risks and benefits are all fairly shared.” It surprises me though when even an evolutionary biologist such as David Sloan Wilson (see his Darwin’s Cathedral) is willing to refer to sociologists, such as Durkheim and Rodney Stark, to bolster a (at first glance) similar argument about how the purpose of religion is to unite human groups. It seems then that some might be happy to think that this is because of our status as adaptive organisms, while others (such as most technoprogressives, apparently) prefer to rally around democratic norms, without feeling any need to dress them up in religious garb. Some sociologists might use the Thomas theorem, or, what basically amounts to the same thing, Robert K Merton’s “Matthew Effect,” to frame these respective preferences as examples of a self-fulfilling prophecy—i.e. if people define a situation as real, it will be real in its consequences. I can see some benefits of this pragmatic stance as far as facilitating the kind of broad coalition-building upon which democratic politics depends is concerned; at least when understood as “the art of the possible.” I sense though that this kind of approach falls well short of the kind of social constructivism you prefer, right?
You raise a couple of interesting points here. First, on the role of religion as human motivator: The world-religions really divide on this point. The great non-Abrahamic religions of the East, the so-called the ‘wisdom religions’ (Hinduism, Buddhism, Confucianism, Taoism), do indeed orient people in ways that might fit a story of evolutionary adaptation, since they aim to get people to reach equilibrium with their environment, typically with minimum force applied to those concerned. In contrast, the Abrahamic religions are all about living up to God’s standards, which invariably means a radical transformation of ourselves and our world; hence, the great stress that especially Christianity and Islam place on deciding to believe –i.e. drawing a line on your past life and embarking upon a new one fully of uncertainties yet no less purposeful for that. This empowering sense of religion is not easily explained in evolutionary terms because it calls for us to continually de-stabilise our default mode of being, most notably by developing moral commitments to those outside our immediate family and community, which would otherwise be the locus of concern dictated by the Darwinian logic of survival.
This brings us to the second point: While it is certainly fair to describe the Abrahamic concern for a ‘universal humanity’ to be ‘artificial’ as opposed to ‘natural’ (which explains the need to enshrine this concern as an explicit code of conduct), the ‘social constructions’ one subsequently engages in do not necessarily bear fruit immediately or even directly. In that respect, the pragmatic payoff of living, say, a Christian life is typically not realized in proportion to the effort put in -- that’s one operational way of defining reality as ‘independent’ of us. Indeed, as in the case of Calvinists, the benefits may be deferred for one’s entire biological life, only to be redeemed in the afterlife. As I suggested in answer to the previous question, the history of science and technology in the modern period partakes of this mode of thought, so we continue remaking the world in our image and likeness, always presuming that the benefits outweigh the costs, even as the columns of the our collective existential balance sheet mount up differently. Recalling Karl Popper’s famous distinction in The Poverty of Historicism (1957) between ‘prediction’ and ‘prophecy’ as a rough-and-ready way of distinguishing science from religion, I would stress that our commitment to science itself (as opposed to its particular theories) is in the mode of a prophetic religion. Indeed, Popper would be in agreement, since he believed that the faith-based nature of science was demonstrated by our belief that we could reach the truth – as opposed to a sceptical dead end -- by engaging in the resolute elimination of error
Ok, that explains why you think we need a Religion 2.0 to complement the conception of Humanity 2.0. I notice that one of your co-panellists in the discussion on Humanity 2.0 to be held at the RSA on October 6th is the renowned fantasy fiction author, committed socialist, and atheist, China Miéville. I expect Miéville will go out of his way to emphasise (what he would most likely regard as) the inherent limitations of any reliance on liberal democratic institutions in the face of the powerful logics of commodification driving the technoscience behind genetics, nanotechnology, and robotics. Unequivocal arguments along these lines have also been issued by critical theorists such as Frédéric Vandenberghe and Glenn Rikowski.
I only mention these points because on page 215 you write: “Marxism as the putative ‘no discount zone’ failed because, in the end, the labour theory of value provided at most a regulative ideal towards which an existing society might aim but little guidance in either identifying or redressing ‘differences that make a difference’ in such a society. In this respect, Marxism lacked a distinctly sociological sensibility, which is perhaps most evident in the movement’s eschatological impulse to end history formally and create society anew.” You then go on to give a positive account of the tax system as a social democratic solution for “administering justice across classes and generations.” What is the intended take-home message for Marxists here? Should the book be understood as providing this needed “sociological sensibility” to Marxist critiques of transhumanism etc, or is it implying that the best we can probably hope for in the future is managed affluence—meaning that piecemeal reforms are the most realistic means of curbing the excesses of what you refer to as “bioliberalism”?
First, I must confess that I do not follow the Deleuzians as closely as others do, but I notice that they do tend toward the mealy-mouthed when dealing with Humanity 2.0. Really now, what is this backhanded ‘let’s hope for a post-human that’s not inhuman’? Why not call it by its proper name and fight for it: ‘transhumanism’? We should be about promoting as widely as possible the aspects of our being that we find most admirable and take collective responsibility for the consequences. Of course, the political implications of this idea are far from obvious and are bound to be controversial. Still, the transhumanists start the argument the right way round – instead of looking at the world as we find it and then expressing our disappointments, regrets and fears in ever so artful ways, which seems to be the Deleuzian policy, as they simply take the animal side of the argument as given. In this I am very much with the Fichtean idealist roots of Marxism, with its proactive stance towards the intelligently guided human will.
Where Marxism has faltered – and interestingly my criticism applies more to Marx’s so-called ‘humanist’ early work than his later more ‘scientistic’ phase – has been in its essentialism towards our ‘species being’, which is ever on the lookout for the negative consequences of alienation but seemingly blind to the positive consequences of having a legally protected sphere of free exchange. In this respect, Marx continued down the path of Rousseau beyond the point that Kant got off. Because Kant does not identify our unique potential for autonomy with the sheer possession of a human body, he lacks Marx’s fastidiousness over whether individuals are selling their birth right by acceding to substandard work conditions. For Kant, what matters is the state of mind in which such a decision is taken, not the impact that the decision might have on the future condition of the body. If I were of a more panglossian frame of mind, I would be tempted to say that capitalism has actually helped people to think about their humanity more sharply by forcing them continually rethink what is essential and accidental in terms of the sort of being that they aspire to be, since any advancement will invariably involve selling some part of oneself.
The problem I raise about Marxism’s ‘sociological deficit’, so to speak, relates to the sharp disjunction, even schizophrenia, in the Marxist literature between the Communist ideal of human equality, understood as a state of universal emancipation, and whatever means it might take – be they parliamentary or revolutionary -- to reach it. For a political movement that is officially committed to ‘the unity of theory and practice’, Marxism has had a long and embarrassing tendency of not owning up to the history of its own practice, a point that eventually led Popper to revoke Marxism’s scientific credentials. Marxist theorists routinely distance themselves from both the peaceful and violent sides of that history, as ‘failures of the revolution’: Social democrats are co-opted wimps, and totalitarians over-the-top monsters. Against this backdrop, one comes to appreciate the distinctiveness of Lenin who clearly wanted to honour both Marx’s philosophical integrity and political animus in his own practice. But of course this meant killing people when they got in the way of the dialectic. I talk about ‘theodicy’ in this context as well. While Marx himself would have known that Hegel got his ironic view of world-history from Leibniz’s theodicy, his followers have been reluctant to admit the full force of this lineage, which entails accepting that people will have to suffer before they become better.
One of the most vocal advocates of “democratic transhumanism” is James Hughes (author of Citizen Cyborg). In an article entitled “The Politics of Transhumanism,” Hughes worryingly refers to a small group of neo-Nazis who have attached themselves to the movement. This might be an ideal segue-way for Roger Griffin, who sent the following response:
ROGER GRIFFIN: I do not wish to comment on the book as a whole. I notice, however, several passages that refer to the ongoing historical significance of the Third Reich with respect to how scientific developments might be harnessed to a progressive future. For the sake of brevity, I will confine my remarks to the following passage, which appears on page 244:
"Albeit often in defence of odious policies, this strand of the American political tradition has consistently upheld the legitimacy of social action taken by self-organising individuals. Can such a story be told even for Nazi Germany, in spite of the enormity of the suffering it caused? If we wish to continue including the Nazis as part of the history of humanity – as opposed to the history of nature – then the answer must be yes, however difficult at first glance that may seem. Put bluntly, we must envisage the prospect of a transformation in the normative image of Nazi Germany comparable to what Barrington Moore described for the French Revolution. This is not easy. The makeover Moore observed occurred over a couple of generations, and in that same amount of time there have been only the barest hints of Nazi rehabilitation. But hints there are, helped along by the death of those with first-hand experience of Nazism. To be sure, some areas of Nazi science that did not figure prominently in the Second World War – such as space travel, ecology and cancer research – were easily, if somewhat surreptitiously, assimilated by the Allies. But even in the case of the Nazi science of ‘racial hygiene’, there is a dawning realisation that ‘eugenics’ and ‘genetic modification’ more generally have been always integral to progressive normative agendas. In that case Nazi science policies are perhaps best seen as opportunistically extreme versions of tendencies long present and accepted by the intellectual vanguard of Western culture. Lest this speculation seem, once again, too panglossian, it is worth noting that Nazi Germany promoted itself in just this way – with considerable success in the international media – before the presentation of evidence for the Holocaust. If one is inclined to think, as I am, that the Holocaust was produced by the exigencies of war rather than intrinsic to the Nazi agenda, then a key to recovering the ‘good’ in Nazism might be to rewind history to the 1920s and 1930s when the movement appeared to offer the promise of a progressive future. Back then the Holocaust did not appear to be an inevitable outcome of Nazism, which in turn enabled observers to see Nazis as fruitfully extending existing scientific agendas" (cf. Fuller 2006b: chap. 14).
This is a curious passage: historians have long been working on integrating Nazism within human history rather than demonizing it simply as ‘evil’ or ‘barbaric’ or ‘monstrous’. A whole industry of sophisticated Third Reich history exists, prominent representatives of which writing in English are Richard Evans, Michael Burleigh, and Ian Kershaw. So Nazism is already an integral part of human history.
But rehabilitating Nazism, Stalinism, the Pol Pot regime etc is quite another issue. Germans have been rehabilitated and reaccepted into the fold of civilized humanity, but somehow accommodating Hitler’s regime as a positive episode of human history is simply perverse. It sounds as if the author wants to cherry pick aspects of Nazism which are somehow ‘progressive’ in order to graft Nazism back into the Western scheme of ‘progress’. This would be a deeply mythic exercise which has a lot to do with how ‘the general public’, ‘collective consciousness’ digests human atrocities (First World War, WW2, 9/11) or forgets them (US genocide in North America, the Slave Trade etc). Digesting them reminds me of how a snake eats a dog, namely by dislocating its jaw.
Who is the ‘we’ that must envisage a transformation of the normative image of the Third Reich? Historiography is not about normalizing but understanding. Cancer research is not about normalizing cancer but understanding its mechanisms.
Unsurprisingly then, I disagree with the claim that eugenics has ‘always been integral to progressive normative agendas’. Eugenics grew up in the 19th century and in its ‘positive’ but non-coercive concern with health has been embraced within enlightened social policies the world over. But the negative eugenics of the sort that sterilizes and kills which lay at the heart of Nazi social engineering has been utterly discredited as a perverse, deeply irrational ideology which acquired the deeply pathological momentum of a crusade against decadence for some believers in science as a substitute religion on which to base a healthy society and had long been rejected by humanists.
I also have considerable reservations about the claim that the Nazi eugenic campaign was due to the exigencies of war because it borders dangerously on revisionist history (e.g. of someone like Ernst Nolte) which rehabilitates Nazism by using a range of arguments that rework the facts. The works of Browning and Kershaw offer a great deal of historical evidence to undermine any relationship between the exigencies of war and the Holocaust.
The historical fact is that the Nazi war on communism, democracy and what were deemed ideological and racial enemies was integral to the whole being and purpose of the Nazi revolution, the premise for the construction of a new order and a new Nazi empire purged of undesirable elements/filth. Auschwitz was called “the anus of Europe” by the Nazis because it excreted Jews, and the genocide continued to the last days of the war long after the exigencies of war had stopped.
My concern is that the revisionist thrust of this passage is basically scrambling the valid point that Nazism is an integral chapter of the history of modernity (which does NOT mean something intrinsically good). I hope the author might consider a close reading of Bauman’s The Holocaust and Modernity (and even my Modernism and Fascism) as a corrective.
In sum, I would strongly argue that there was no 'good' in Nazism because (from a non-Nazi perspective) all the good was at the expense of bad (persecution, torture, the destruction of lives, genocide etc) and this ‘bad’ was integral to the ‘good’. It is possible to imagine counterfactually a French Revolution without the Terror and even a Russian Revolution and a Maoist Revolution that did not cause scores of millions of deaths and create vast systems of prison camps and oceans of suffering (just): but the revolutions undertaken by Hitler and Pol Pot were destined in their very conception to mass produce atrocities, and there can be no ‘rehabilitation’ of a regime that does this, just de-demonization by humanistic historians interested in making sense of history rather than trying to cling desperately onto the mast of the Ship of Enlightenment as it is battered by the waves of the ‘storm of progress’.
This is a very interesting and perhaps telling line of inquiry. Roger is certainly right that I disagree with Bauman’s The Holocaust and Modernity (I briefly critiqued it in The New Sociological Imagination but merely ignore it in Humanity 2.0), and we certainly disagree about the role of eugenics in the history of progressive politics – which is something I raise not only at the end of Humanity 2.0 (as noted by Roger) but throughout the book, especially chapter one, where I note the generally strong support for eugenics on the part of the Fabian socialists who were behind the funding of the UK’s first sociology chair, at the London School of Economics in 1907. This was no fluke but quite consistent with the biopolitics surrounding the establishment of welfare states throughout Europe. It’s no accident that eugenics originated with a self-identified progressive, Francis Galton, and his work was translated into German by Otto Neurath, then a young socialist associated with the Vienna Circle (i.e. not some disgruntled racist Junker). Moreover, the political economist William Beveridge, while LSE director, and just before he created the British welfare state, got the Rockefeller Foundation to fund a chair in ‘social biology’ that would operate as both a mass data gatherer of vital statistics of the body politic and a theoretical foundation for the social sciences. This move proved unpopular and ultimately failed, but for reasons unrelated to matters of genocide. A book due out next year by a young historian (for which I wrote the Foreword) goes through this history quite carefully, in an attempt to explain why British sociology so thoroughly turned its back on biology, even though the country was seen as very much in the vanguard at the dawn of the 20th century: Chris Renwick, British Sociology’s Lost Biological Roots (Palgrave Macmillan, 2012).
Once we set aside the assumption that the Holocaust is a necessary consequence or ultimate expression of eugenics – in other words, once we refuse to let our current moral response to the Holocaust colour our understanding of all the preceding relevant history – it should be pretty clear that eugenics was a left-wing project, both in its ‘negative’ and ‘positive’ forms. I don’t deny that people were sterilised without their consent or appropriate legal representation. To be sure, this is very much to be regretted. However, given the routine violation of human dignity that has attended the history of scientific medicine more generally, I doubt that those episodes alone would have warranted the censoriousness with which people like Roger regard eugenics. Clearly the Holocaust is driving his understanding of an entire scientific project that had promised a gradual, collective, empirically monitored and politically accountable upgrading of the human condition. This is precisely what attracted the Fabians (whose name comes from the Roman general who beat Hannibal by not acting impulsively). While virtually all social reformers of the late 19th and early 20th centuries were calling for greater education and improvement of living conditions as vehicles of social transformation, there was also a general recognition that people with right capacities were also needed to make maximum use of those opportunities, understood as choices that such people could make for themselves without excessive state intervention. In short, the eugenicists committed themselves to building a society whose members were ‘fit to be free’, you might say. Ideologically speaking, I see this project as treating the human gene pool as collectively owned property, whose state-managed cultivation aims to produce people capable of flourishing in a liberal society. You may find this vision heroic or scary or both, but I believe that developments across the sciences and technologies increasingly beckon us to revive this project in a new key, ‘Eugenics 2.0’, if you will. ‘Transhumanism’, a coinage of the eugenicist Julian Huxley, is one of the popular labels under which it nowadays travels. Put that way, humans are clearly claiming some of (the Abrahamic) God’s powers for themselves. But in the early 21st century this should be no cause for alarm. After all, modernity has been all about prior sacrileges being upgraded into the sincerest form of flattery to the deity.
As for my wishing to ‘rehabilitate’ Nazism, yes, in the sense that their activities come to be understood as having served larger goals that in the long run have benefited humanity—in particular, by testing the limits of our knowledge and being. ‘National socialism’ was commonly used for the nation-based welfare states of Scandinavia that inspired Hitler. This was to do with the accuracy of the phrase, especially in contradistinction to a Trotsky-style free-floating World Communist movement that denied the possibility of socialism in one country. We need to put our understanding of Nazism back into that context. I am not trying to rewrite Nazi motives, but write them more completely -- and I freely admit that their motives became corrupt by the time of the Holocaust. My aim is to broaden the context for assessing the consequences of Nazi actions, something very much in the spirit of ‘theodicy’, that is, God’s sense of justice. It involves treating every act – however prima facie noble or ignoble – as ultimately no more and no less than a means to a more exalted end, namely, completion of the divine plan, in which we are the principal agent. This is the moral horizon of Humanity 2.0. At the very least, it allows us to get the most mileage out of the Nazi experience – which, like it or not, we’re stuck with -- by refusing to set up artificial barriers to our treating it charitably, perhaps in the spirit of ‘it was a dirty job, but someone had to do it’. Indeed, maybe the Nazis reveal that even God must operate with dirty hands.
My inclination to forgive is not as crazy as it may sound. Indeed, the memory of the Holocaust is nowadays kept alive by a kind of suspended animation of historical consciousness that prevents it from being properly integrated into our collective psyche. Recall that the Arab-Israeli War of 1967, which resulted in Israel’s deeply unpopular redrawing of its territorial boundaries, unleashed what Peter Novick and Norman Finkelstein have provocatively described as the ‘Holocaust Industry’, namely, a concerted effort to ensure that the Holocaust’s enormity was never forgotten. This project, which continues to engage some of social theory’s most sophisticated minds, is admitted by all sides to be an uphill struggle, since our default collective psychology is to forget, if not exactly forgive. To be sure, I don’t believe in forgetting Nazi atrocities. On the contrary, I believe that they remain pedagogically useful for illustrating what it means to realize long-held scientific desires with impunity and from which we now continue to benefit, even though we cannot see ourselves as having committed the original acts involved. But in the final analysis, the apparent moral and epistemic certitude with which Roger expresses his views leads me to two conclusions: (1) even today the history of science has yet to be properly integrated into the history of modernity; (2) our understanding of the causes and significance of the Holocaust is still very much distorted by a preoccupation with its most abnormal and abhorrent aspects – as if simply creating moral distance from the Holocaust were sufficient to establish our own superiority.
GREGOR WOLBRING: How can we mainstream ableism studies into academic and public discourses given that this lens gives us a fresh clue on dynamics and consequences?
According to ‘ableism’, the mark – if not stigmata – of the transhuman condition is that everyone, not just the conventionally disabled, will come to feel ‘always already’ disabled. This is because the increasing demand – and ultimately supply – or bio-enhancements will cause the standards of normative performance to shift upward. In effect, ‘being normal’ itself becomes what welfare economists call a ‘positional good’, which is to say, its value is tied to its relative scarcity: Thus, the value of being clever lies in being cleverer than others. The great virtue of ableism is that it places the questions surrounding our biotechnological enhancement squarely in the realm of political economy, very much as Francis Galton and William Beveridge thought about eugenics. Thus, contrary to the popular rhetoric of tranhumanist enthusiasts, transhumanist desires are not simply free-floating ideals or freely chosen identities, but emergent features of a fluid political and scientific situation concerning our future.
Gregor asks about how to make ableism studies ‘mainstream’. My general answer to ‘mainstreaming’ questions is to provide an adequate backstory in our common intellectual and cultural history. Like any recently identified movement, ‘ableism’ suffers from ‘the shock of the new’, which in turn instinctively inclines people to respond to it as alien, if not outright threatening. Ableism may be especially prone to this treatment because of the deep challenges it poses to how we define ‘normal’ and ‘disabled’ bodies. However, in Humanity 2.0, I observe that the hopes and anxieties generated by an ableist mentality is traceable to a semantic innovation of the fourteenth century Oxford Franciscan, John Duns Scotus, in discussing God’s properties. Scotus basically detached each of the divine properties from the deity so as to analyse each of them as independent capabilities that are developed finitely in humans but infinitely in God. For example, from the idea of ‘all-powerful father’ was derived the idea of ‘power’ as such as a dimension in terms of which God indefinitely surpasses us. Moreover, Scotus suggested that in humans all of these potentially divine dimensions are developed to varying degrees, and of course none to anything approaching the divine limit. While it may be easy to say that God is all-powerful, all-loving and all-knowing, just based on the range of humans that history has put on offer, it is difficult to imagine the sort of being in whom all those capabilities would be developed to such a great extent. Indeed, a major source of human misery is the uneven development of such capabilities within ourselves, whereby we are overdeveloped in some and underdeveloped in others. Ableism provides a high-tech secular way of revisiting those ontological concerns of the High Middle Ages.
Is there anything you'd like to add?
As my response to the several of the questions here indicate, proceeding to ‘Humanity 2.0’ requires a re-engagement with Western theology on at least three nowadays neglected fronts:
- Theology as a discipline dedicated to human empowerment in search of divine reunion, which involves our emancipation from concerns that are limited to ‘this world’, however that phrase is defined. Such is the basis of modern ideas of progress.
- Theology as a discipline that encourages humans to take their own words literally and hence their ideas as blueprints or models for reality, things projected outward into the world rather than simply allowed to pass before the mind’s eye without consequence.
- Theology as the great recycler of meaning and rationalizer of action by providing the most comprehensive framework in terms of which anything may be understood as contributing to the global optimisation of divine creation.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)